West Indian Constitutional Discourse: A Poetics of Reconstruction

AuthorSimeon C.R. McIntosh
ProfessionProfessor Emeritus of Law at Howard University, Washington, DC
Pages306-373
West Indian Constitutional
Discourse: A Poetics of
Reconstruction
Introduction – A Question of Constitutional Image
An oath is of no moment, being not took
Before a true and lawful magistrate
That hath authority over him that swears. - Shakespeare (Henry VI)
It is still our wont in the Commonwealth Caribbean,1 on the view that
Queen Elizabeth II of Britain continues to be our queen, to pledge allegiance
to her. Every Member of Parliament, like the Governor-General, must first
take the Oath of Allegiance to Her Majesty , before assuming office. Thus the
Barbadian intellectual, Sir James Tudor, writes:
We [Barbados] are a nation state because, together with our other
attributes of sovereignty , she is our Queen. Ours is a territory that came
into history neither by conquest, nor by cession, nor by an exchange, but
as a realm discovered by Englishmen and settled in the name of an English
King, before the designations ‘Great Britain’ or ‘United Kingdom’ ever
entered the history books. The Crown is therefore the oldest institution
in Barbados, with Parliament coming next.
It is on this understanding that Barbados entered history as an English
realm which makes me a monarchist. Had I not understood and accepted
this as an indefeasible truth, I could not have had a career in the politics
of my country and a place in its Parliament. I could never have taken the
Oath of Allegiance to the Queen if she were only Queen of the United
Kingdom and nothing else.2
Such reasoning seems rather nonsensical for at least two reasons. First,
Mr Tudor was writing as a citizen of independent Barbados; therefore,
notwithstanding Barbados’s entry into history as an ‘English realm’, Mr
307
West Indian Constitutional Discourse: A Poetics of Reconstruction
Tudor seems incognizant of the break in the historical continuity of British
sovereignty wrought by the political independence of Barbados. Second,
the historical fact of Barbados having been claimed for the King of England
would certainly have brought Barbados under the dominion of the English
Crown and would have made everyone living in the territory a ‘subject’ of
the English Monarch – at least until political independence. But this hardly
makes one a monarchist as an ‘indefeasible truth’. For the simple fact is that
for one to claim to be a monarchist is to argue that monarchical rule is the
best form of political rule. Thus, Mr Tudor may have gleaned from experience
that monarchical rule is the most appealing form of political rule, and, on this
score, he can indeed be said to be a ‘monarchist’. But it would be somewhat
of a non sequitur for him to claim that he is a monarchist because he was,
from birth, a subject of the English Crown. If, assuming arguendo, Barbados
is still under the dominion of the ‘Crown’, then Mr David Comissiong,3 who
disavows the Monarchy and could not therefore be said to be a monarchist,
is, equally, (like Mr Tudor), a subject of Queen Elizabeth II.
This discussion, however, hardly suggests its earth-shaking importance,
for it puts in high relief one of the foundational interpretive issues in
West Indian constitutional law: the central question of our constitutional
image.4 It is this image, a shared consciousness among judges, lawyers,
scholars and citizens alike, which functions epistemologically to shape our
constitutional discourse by defining the scope of our inquiry, the categories
in terms of which we frame such inquiry, and informing the issues posed
by the constitutional text – issues regarding the institutional arrangement of
political authority, and the fundamental rights of the citizen, and the citizens
standing to challenge governmental policy.5
It is rather the common understanding that, with few exceptions,6 all
of the independent states of the Commonwealth Caribbean have retained
the Queen of England as their head of state. This is taken to mean that, like
Britain itself, they are all constitutional monarchies. There has been among
them a common practice to find the Queen’s continuing presence in the
post-independence constitutional order in such language that ‘the executive
authority of [Barbados] shall vest in Her Majesty The Queen, Her Heirs
and Successors alike’.7 Such a fundamental misreading of the constitutional
relationship between the independent Commonwealth Caribbean and
the British Sovereign rather betrays a passive acquiescence in an unargued
doctrinal position, the product of an historically situated discourse of
power-relation, (coloniser and colonised), that has managed to impose its
Reading Text and Polity
308
own normative categories on West Indian constitutional thought to the point
of silencing the claims of critical reason and hermeneutic reflection.8
An eminent student of West Indian constitutional law, A.R. Carnegie,
has submitted that British legislative power over a territory disappears in a
single event at the moment of independence. There therefore remains, he
reasons, the theoretical problem of giving an explanation in legal theory
of the manner in which a power ceased to exist when it was intrinsic to the
theory that the power could not be abdicated. But we know that this has
happened even if we cannot explain how it happened.9 And legally, in respect
of those countries ‘where the monarchy has been retained, all this meant no
change in the legal power of the Crown, but merely in the identification of
the sources of the advice the Crown takes.’10 On this view, it would seem, the
Crown has the same status in the post-Independence West Indian political
order as it had in the pre-independence political order.
The issue as framed by Professor Carnegie is not happily put. The
problem is fundamentally jurisprudential: how to explain the end of imperial
rule in a territory and the conceptualization of that territory ‘as if it has
been reconstituted as an independent sovereign state. More simply put, the
problem is one of explaining the removal of British sovereignty from the West
Indies upon their political independence and, therefore, their reconstitution
as sovereign states. In other words, any adequate historical/political narrative
or explanandum that would be faithful to the cognitive values of its genus,
and which affects to explain our advance from colonial status to political
independence, must inevitably take account of the corresponding shift
in the constitutional position of the British Sovereign vis-à-vis the former
colonies. For it is precisely this sort of shift that we want explained; and an
explanandum describes not only an event – something that happens, political
independence, say – but rather a – change.11 Thus, West Indian constitutional
analysis must apply its best efforts to the task of rational reconstruction in
order to explain what is conceptually entailed in this movement from colonial
status to political independence; and this requires that reason be allowed full
scope for the exercise of a critical hermeneutics that distances itself from the
currency of accepted ideas and the unthinking doctrinal adherence to the
‘scriptural’ reading of our constitutional texts. For we could not possibly
begin to render an adequate reading of our constitutional texts without
acknowledging the tacit values, the structure of shared meanings, beliefs and
pre-understandings, that make up the enabling background of each and every
interpretive act.12

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT