Introduction. Revolutionary Legality

AuthorSimeon C.R. McIntosh
ProfessionProfessor of Jurisprudence and Dean, Faculty of Law, University of the West Indies at Cave Hill, Barbados
Pages11-44
Introduction | xi
INTRODUCTION
REVOLUTIONARY LEGALITY
The concept of revolutionary legality1 would seem a serious
contradiction in terms; for the sense in which the term is used in
jurisprudence and political theory means that a revolution is
understood to be an illegal act, often the violent overthrow of an
established legal order and the institution of a new sovereignty in its
place, which, in due course, may become a valid legal order. It is now
an historical truth that revolution is one of the principal means of
founding a new state; and the United States of America stands as
the most successful example in modern history of this truth. As Paul
Ricoeur suggests, ‘[revolutionary] violence brings onto the stage of
history … new States, dominant civilizations, ruling classes;’2 ‘[t]heir
violent birth then becomes resorbed in the new legitimacy which they
foster and consolidate.’3 But this new ‘republic,’ this new ‘legality’ is
marked from its inception by violence which was successful. Indeed,
‘All nations, all powers, and all regimes are born this way.’4 What,
then, becomes a critical question for jurisprudence and political theory
is whether the new ‘legality’ is capable of being a State of justice and
law. This is a question of the moral legitimacy of the State; ‘the belief
in the rightfulness of the State, in its authority to issue commands,
so that those commands are obeyed not simply out of fear or self-
interest, but because they are believed in some sense to have moral
authority….’5
The principal proponent of the theory of revolutionary legality in
twentieth century legal philosophy was the Austrian-born philosopher,
the late Professor Hans Kelsen. His theory of revolutionary legality
xii | Kelsen in the Grenada Court
was articulated as part of his general theory of law, which he dubbed:
‘a pure theory of law’. As Professor Michael Hartney suggests,
Kelsen’s work, the Pure Theory of Law, ‘was intended to set out the
conceptual framework which would allow any exposition of the law of
a given jurisdiction to be scientific.’6 Law had to be cleansed of certain
noxious influences, such as ‘a vestigial belief in natural law,’ in order
to be scientific.7 Thus, for Kelsen, ‘a sound philosophy should allow
us to grasp the essence of law and avoid confusing it with other
disciplines, as traditional jurisprudence does when it confuses law
and morality.…’8
In his theorizing, ‘Kelsen also sought to offer a corrective to a
problem in traditional jurisprudence’s account of a legal system as a
collection of disparate elements. Rather, he wished to show that there
is a basic unity beneath any apparent diversity within a legal system,
evidenced in certain dualities of public and private law, creation of
law (by lawmakers) and application of law (by courts), municipal law
and international law.’9 For Kelsen, the unity of a legal system is
guaranteed by a basic norm which validates all the other norms
comprising the system. Law is a system of norms. Thus, a legal system
is a normative order.
But law is not a normative order in the moral sense. Rather, it is
to say that legal norms are not descriptive statements of empirical
reality, but are instead a set of ‘meanings’ or interpretations of acts
of will that are directed toward the conduct of others.10 Legal norms
are however not addressed to the subjects of the legal system; they
are rather addressed to the officials, and direct them to impose
sanctions under certain conditions.11 In sum, then, legal norms are
‘ought’ statements, though not in the moral sense, and they merely
serve to indicate that certain legal consequences should follow from
certain actions.
But there remains the problem of grounding the validity of a legal
system, given that Kelsen’s basic norm is a presupposition in juristic
thinking. The basic norm is presupposed in order to ground the validity
of all the legal norms forming a positive legal order. As a
Introduction | xiii
presupposition, the basic norm has no content whatsoever; it merely
assures that there is a normative basis for the validity of legal rules.
Specifically, then, the problem is one of grounding the validity of the
constitution, since the constitution is, in reality, the highest positive
norm of an existing legal system, and which regulates and determines
the creation of all other enacted norms of the system. It is therefore
the constitution that, in reality, gives unity to a legal system.
Kelsen saw the problem of the validity of the constitution as a
transcendental-logical deduction, which, in order to avoid a situation
of infinite regress, stops at the historically first constitution. Thus,
‘when we regard a legal order as grounded we must – logically must
– be posting a “historically first constitution” together with a socially
prevailing “basic norm” conferring on the first constitution’s
promulgators the authority to make it to be the law, and thereby
obligate the country’s posterity … to grant the force of law to everything
that has issued from or pursuant to a chain of amending clauses
depending from the first constitution.’12 As Kelsen puts it:
If one asks what is the basis of the validity of a given constitution, the
answer may be that that constitution came into existence through
amendment of a preceding constitution, and that this amendment was
made in a way that constitutional amendments on the basis of the
preceding constitution have to be made. Thus one can refer back to a
historically first constitution. This historically first constitution too is, to
begin with, the subjective meaning of an act of will or a number of acts
of will; and if one asks why the subjective meaning of the act creating
the constitution is also its objective meaning – that is, a valid norm –
or, in other words, what is the basis of the validity of this norm, the
answer is: because one presupposes, as jurist, that one ought to conduct
oneself as the historically first constitution prescribes. This is the basic
norm.13
It means, then, that the validity of the historically first constitution
of a State is founded on the presupposed validity of the Basic Norm.
But in order to ‘grasp the essence of the basic norm, one must,
above all, keep in mind that it refers directly to a particular constitution
that has in fact been laid down, whether created by custom or by

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT