Majoritarian and Consociational Systems of Governance: Paradigms in Conflict

AuthorSelwyn Ryan
Pages175-194
Paradigms in Conflict 175
Do institutions matter more than agency or political culture?1 Do kings
make constitutions or is the reverse the case? If the latter, what kind of
institutional arrangements best facilitate good governance? Should powers be
separated, or should one opt for institutions which share power as obtains in
the American political system? Political systems come in many institutional
varieties. Amidst the institutional welter, one discerns two broad paradigms. In
the one, power is concentrated while in the other, power is shared. These two
broad paradigmatic expressions of political power are informed by “visions”
and epistemic assumptions about the nature of political man and his capacity
for justice and good governance (Sowell 1987). One view is that man is basically
good, that he is not the enemy of other men and that he or his political
representatives should and could be entrusted with power. As such, one should
not try to fetter man, and by extension his political institutions, with too many
“iron cages” or checks and balances. Man, Rousseau complained, “is born free
and is everywhere in chains”.
Others, like William Godwin and the Marquis de Condorcet, shared the
dominant Enlightenment view that man was basically good and capable of a
great deal of human understanding. Natural man was not to be confused with
existing man who was corrupted by prejudices, artificial passions, social and
religious customs and institutions. Godwin felt that man was perfectible, and
that the task at hand was to “wake the sleeping virtues of mankind”. Good
governance does not therefore require prudential “trade-offs” between men
with conflicting and mercenary interests which have to be reconciled. Godwin,
Condorcet and Rousseau thus envisaged a political system in which the interests
of each would become identified with the interests of all, i.e. the “general will”.
Man will act in the interest of the collectivity and not in response to some
ulterior motive or in terms of the workings of some invisible or hidden hand as
Adam Smith claimed (Sowell 1987:25).
The competing paradigm held that political man was egotistic and driven
majorItarIan anD consocIatIonal
systems of governance: paraDIgms
In conflIct
SELWYN RYAN
CHAPTER ten
176 GOVERNANCE: THEORETICAL ASPECTS
by selfish appetites, and that the political system and its formal expression in
the state should be informed by this understanding of man’s true nature. This
view of man was best articulated by Thomas Hobbes and later on by the American
authors of the Federalist Papers. Hobbes’ formula for dealing with man in what
he called a “state of nature” as he understood it was to create an absolutist state
in which the sovereign was the “Mortal God” and all powerful. The sovereign
“Leviathan” combined in his person the roles of the executive and the legislature
and, in effect, defined what the consensus was. His role as sovereign definer
was to maintain order and create the environment in which men went about
the business of amassing wealth. He created civil society and not the other way
around. He determined what was truth and what was false and subversive.
Truth was contextual and nominal, not essential or foundational. For Hobbes,
peace and order were the sine qua non for good government. If there is no one to
wield the sword coercively, neither civil society nor state was possible.
Covenants without the sword are but words. . . The bonds of words are too
weak to bridle man’s ambition, avarice, anger, and other passions without
the fear of some coercive power . . . without which there is neither state nor
civil society but only a headless multitude . . .Nothing less than the chains
of despotism can restrain men from destroying one another (cited in Frisch
1970:62).
The fathers of the American Constitution, like Alexander Hamilton and
James Madison, were in the main heirs to the Hobbesiam tradition in terms of
how man was imagined. Unlike Hobbes, however, they opted for a system of
governance which sought to control both man and the sovereign. They sought,
as Madison put it, to find a “republican remedy for the diseases most incident to
republican governance”. They were thus consensual as opposed to authoritarian
or majoritarian democrats. Alexander Hamilton, for example, did not consider
political man to be perfectible or driven by concerns for the public good. This
notion, he felt, “was more ardently to be wished than seriously to be expected”.
One thus needed political systems in which ambition could checkmate ambition,
and in which greed would neutralise greed. As Hamilton put it:
it may be a reflection on human nature that such devices should be necessary
to control the abuses of government. But what is government itself but the
greatest of all reflections on human nature.
If man was good, if he was the angel he was said to be, government would not be
necessary. As Hamilton asked rhetorically:
why has government been instituted at all? Because the passions of men

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT